The Wall Street Journal reporting Peter Singer's forthcoming book tells us:
In his latest book, "The Life You Can Save," Mr. Singer argues that failing to donate money to help the roughly 1 billion people suffering from poverty and preventable diseases is a moral offense equivalent to standing by as a child drowns because you don't want to ruin a nice pair of shoes.
Equivalent. But how bad is that I wonder? Given that Singer is on record saying there is "no intrinsic moral difference between killing and allowing to die" he would seem committed to saying that failing to donate is morally equivalent to drowning a child. Pretty bad!
Of course, not everyone denies moral significance to the difference between killing and allowing to die. Some philosophers distinguish between "negative" duties (e.g., not to drown children) and positive ones, (e.g., to save children from drowning), holding that positive duties are not as onerous as negative ones. Though, as Judith Jarvis Thomson recently observed,
"... it is one thing to say there is a difference in weight between positive and negative duties, and quite another to say what the source of that difference is. I know of no thoroughly convincing account of its source, and regard the need for one as among the most pressing in all moral theory."
For anyone interested in taking up Thomson's challenge, Singer's equivalence poses a problem. After all, this bystander who stands by while a child drowns (for the sake of his shoes!) is a bad man. Let us not mince words; he is a sonofabitch. The positive moral duty not to behave like such a character must have significant "weight". And if failing in positive duties makes us as bad as that guy, then the difference in "weight" and hence the significance of the positive-negative distinction itself, must be morally slight.
I give negligible amounts to charity. So is Singer calling me a sonofabitch? Apparently. And you too, if you fail to donate money to the starving billion when you could (and you know you could).
Is there any way to defend ourselves? Shelly Kagan, Peter Unger, and now Singer, have written whole books arguing that there is not. Arguing, that is, that if you agree that you have moral obligations to do things like help that drowning child, you must concede that you are likewise obliged to do everything you can to help everyone, everywhere, all the time. If that is so, then it seems we must admit that we are sons of bitches, you and I.
The problem for Singer's position is that none of us believe its conclusion. Not even Singer.
Singer tells the WSJ:
I give a third of my income to Oxfam and other organizations working in the field. I still feel that, as comfortably off as I am, I should be giving more. We still take family vacations to nice places. We could spend time somewhere less expensive. Also, I'm still prepared to have a bottle of wine or go to the theater or to some kind of concert. If you think about what that money can do for people in extreme poverty, it's hard to justify that type of spending.
Hard? Hard! If having that Merlot is really equivalent to standing by while a child drowns (to save your shoes!) isn't it impossible to justify that type of spending?
And yet Singer clearly does not expect us to think he is a sonofabitch. Look at that picture!
We don't begrudge Singer a drink or show now and then. We don't think of him as comparable to the sonofabitch who stands by while a child drowns, still less to someone who drowns a child. Why not?
It seems to me that it must be because the children Singer lets die when he buys his ticket for the show aren't nearby. It is not as if Singer thinks those stage kids in Les Miz are really miserable We assume that Singer, like the rest of us, would be hard pressed to enjoy a drink or a show if he knew there was great misery nearby. But it is easy for all of us to enjoy ourselves even while we know for a fact that there is enormous suffering elsewhere and out of sight. It's easy provided we don't dwell on it. And it is easy not to dwell on it: out of sight, out of mind.
We think the sonofabitch is a bad guy--- whereas Singer, not so much-- because the sonofabitch is letting a nearby kid die, not some out-of-sight abstraction. It’s ignoring this vividly present suffering that makes him such an odious figure. Not so Singer, or the rest of us, who are far from the children we allow to die . Which is why we think that we are not so bad.
Does this make sense? After all as Singer et al never tire of pointing out, mere proximity can't make a moral difference. What matters for the moral assessment of behavior are means and motive. Singer has the means: he could give his pin money to charity as easily as the bad guy could save that drowning child. And while the sight of a drowning child may be psychologically harrowing Singer knows full well the consequences of his actions: he cannot plead ignorance. He chooses self-gratification over saving lives. How can we regard him as morally different from the sonofabitch bystander?
We can't.
I think that Singer is right that failing to send money overseas is morally equivalent to allowing the child to drown. I think that because I think we have no moral obligation to either save the drowning child or the remote starving millions. Absent prior duties imposed by promises or parenthood, I maintain that we have no moral obligation to alleviate the sufferings or enhance the welfare of others. There are no positive moral duties.
I offer our good opinion of Singer and Singer's good opinion of himself (look at that picture), despite his drinks and shows and vacations, as evidence for my view.
Let me hasten to say that I agree that the bystander who watches the child die is a sonofabitch. I am happy to say he is "a bad man". But the sense of "bad" in which this is true is not, I think, a moral one.
Moral right and wrong have to do with actions, with what people do. But we do not think the bystander is a bad guy because he does something morally wrong. Suppose the bystander had stayed at home to polish his shoes. Then he would never have encountered the drowning child and would never had the opportunity to save or refrain from saving it. If you count failing-to-save as "doing a bad thing" then you should agree that, had he stayed home, the bystander would have done one less bad thing that day. If you think the bystander wrongs this child by not saving it when he can, then you should agree that the bystander would not have wronged the child had he just not been standing by.
But the world would not have been a better place -- no one would have been better or better off-- had the bystander stayed home. The child would still be dead and the bystander would still be every bit as much of a sonofabitch as he is in the world where he can save the child but doesn't. He would still be the kind of sonofabitch who would stand by and watch a child drown when he could save it. His actual behavior with respect to the child is relevant only because it reveals what a sonofabitch he is.
The bystander is a sonofabitch because his behavior demonstrates that he has a bad character . I suppose a practitioner of "virtue ethics" would say that his behavior demonstrates that he lacks the virtue of "charity" or perhaps "empathy". I don't entirely disagree: I think charitableness, in its place, is a virtue. But I don't agree that it is a moral or "ethical" virtue.
There are lots of virtues that aren't moral. I think having a sense of humor is a virtue but I wouldn't claim it was a moral virtue (except as a joke). To be convinced that a character trait is morally bad I would require evidence that it disposed its bearer to morally bad behavior. And remember I don't think that the bystander does anything morally bad by doing things like standing by while the child drowns. If you do then you will have a problem with Singer's equivalence: if failing to donate all you can is as unvirtuous as letting that child drown then you are going to have to say that even Singer lacks moral virtue. But look at that picture!
Virtue ethics goes wrong precisely when it aims to be a kind of ethics: as if we could decide the ethics of actions by examining the character of admirable agents. This is not a new idea: Nietzsche took the Christian recipe for being a good person to be deeply repulsive. Heroic charitableness, he thought, does not make you a Hero. But because he insisted on treating his position as a moral one he took this to be a reductio of Christian norms of action (this, I think, is the core of his "critique of morality"). The problem with this is its corollary, which Nietzsche embraced, viz. that True Heroes can literally do no wrong. This runs Singer's mistake in reverse: whereas Singer supposes that behaving like a sonofabitch must mean that you are doing something morally bad, Nietzsche lets his superior men get away with murder. Contemporary virtue ethicists threaten to repeat the mistake-- though their preferred model of the Übermensch is less like Siegfried and more like an Associate Professor of Women’s Studies .
The corrective to Nietzsche is not to deny the reality of heroism but to acknowledge that heroic acting out is not always morally good; just as the corrective to Singer is to note that some behavior, though swinish, is not morally wrong.
So if I don't think the badness of the sonofabitch is moral badness, what sort of disvalue is it?
A.J. Ayer is reported to have once said, of a certain colleague, that he had "...gone bad." Ayer explained, " I don't mean morally bad. I don't use moral language. I mean he's gone bad like an orange goes bad!" I think that's about right. The relevant sort of goodness and badness has more in common with aesthetic value than it does with moral right and wrong. We think the bystander is an ugly customer. He is, among people, as an ugly picture is among pictures.
In calling our evaluation of the bystander’s badness "aesthetic" I am not in the least trying to trivialize it. I do not say (would never say) "merely" aesthetic. The measures by which we judge one person better than another are at the center of human life. They are values by which we choose who to love, who to hate, who to befriend, who to celebrate and who to shun. Few of us make decisions as important as these by asking how much the other gives to Oxfam.
To ask if someone is a good or a bad person is to ask a profoundly different question than to ask whether they do or are disposed to do morally good or bad things. I call the former 'aesthetic' because the logic of 'good person' seems to me to more like that of 'good picture' than 'do gooder'.
Moralists are in the business of dividing in twain: deontologists between good and bad acts; consequentialists among outcomes. But just as it is an aesthetic mistake to think that the job of the critic is to divide all art into two piles it is absurd to think that people monotonically range from saints to sons of bitches. There are good people and bad, just as there are good and bad pictures, but there is more to it than that. Lot's more. Though one will get little help from philosophical moralists in trying to sort it out.
Moral philosophers are characteristically committed to avoiding comparisons of the intrinsic value of persons. The moral point of view, many hold, is constituted by seeing no person, even oneself, as more valuable than any other. It is the "view from nowhere" and no one. And that may indeed be the right stance for resolving questions of moral right and wrong. But this point of view is blind to everything essential to answering a different sort of question: "What kind of person do I want to be?" It is all very well to treat everyone as an end in himself, but we also have to decide how we ourselves want to end up.
Answering that question requires a keen eye for the varieties of persons there are and can be. Again, one will get scant insight on this score from a moralist who can't see a difference between people who don't give to Oxfam and those who would let a child drown. Traditionally the job of describing human values-- understood as the project of saying what gives humans their different values-- belongs to the narrative arts and their critics. And when we look to what they tell us about those values we find that they are largely orthogonal to moral virtue.
Good people can do bad things even when they act in character (the technical term for this phenomenon is 'tragedy'). Killing people is bad. Hamlet kills lots of people and mostly for no good reason. For sure Hamlet does a bad thing when he kills Polonius . But Hamlet is not a bad guy; or if he is, its not just because he kills people and if he isn't, it isn't because he somehow makes up for it by increasing Danish foreign aid.
It seems to me that anyone who would stand by and let a child drown is simply a sonofabitch. But that may only show my lack of imagination. I suspect that Dostoyevsky could have closely described a character doing just that and made him wholly sympathetic. Cormac McCarthy's work is full of sons of bitches who would go out of their way to watch a child drown; but they aren't simple sons of bitches.
And If this seems frivoulous, we have Milgram and Arendt's empirical observations of the disconnect between the quality of character and action. The most evil things can be done by people who no one would judge,apart from their actions, to be bad people. Thus, if you are planning a genocide and looking for staff you can probably find the kind of people you'll need to tend to the details by looking to the office of your local Dean of Arts. Which is not to say that the people you will find there are morally bad, only that they are banal characters. And lucky. Theirs is the moral luck not to have been born in a time and place where -- characters unchanged-- they would placidly have administered atrocity.
It is one thing to avoid doing bad things, another much more difficult and complicated thing to be a good person. I'm suggesting that we avoid confusing these by ceasing to call questions about the value of persons "moral questions". Of course, the weight of tradition is against me in this. As a compromise perhaps we could train ourselves to reserve 'moral' for one sort of goodness and 'ethics' for the other. I don't much care which, but I do think it is important to keep them separate. Confusion on this score can lead one to think that, say, giving to Oxfam makes you a good person and, well... look at that picture.
I agree that moral evaluation of acts and character are distinct. (I think this is the standard position for consequentialists, at least since Parfit's Reasons and Persons.) Curiously, much of your criticism seems to rest on failing to draw this distinction yourself.
In particular, the question of the strength of our moral reasons to act is not the same as the question how blameworthy or "vicious" we would be for failing to act as we should. Singerian 'equivalence' claims only plausibly apply to the former. We have (very strong, pressing) reasons to donate money to charity, just as we do to save nearby drowning children. Nevertheless, the latter failure represents a far greater defect of character: chances are, someone who could watch a child drown before their very eyes is a more callous, morally unconscientious person than one who (like all of us) fails to save every distant life that he might.
I'm not sure what's gained by calling these character assessments "aesthetic" rather than "moral". If someone is unusually insensitive to moral reasons (even when right before their eyes), this is a different kind of character defect than, say, unattractive insecurities or poor humour. And there's a pretty straightforward sense in which the defect is moral in nature.
The issues become much more straightforward if you ditch the outdated deontological language of "duty" and talk directly in terms of moral reasons. Clearly we have moral reason to positively help others in need (if your view denies this, it is simply insane); and greater insensitivity to these reasons thus constitutes a greater moral defect of character.
Later, you discuss "comparisons of the intrinsic value of persons" in a way that again seems to confuse different kinds of evaluation. We can ask how much a person's interests "count", when weighted against others, and here the answer is plausibly "equally!" Alternatively, we can ask whether some people are better people than others -- in the sense of having characters that we have more reason to admire or want in ourselves and others -- in which case the answer is obviously "yes". But having a more (morally or otherwise) admirable character does not entail that your interests count for more. So the fact that moral philosophers offer egalitarian answers to the one question does not entail that they similarly "avoid comparisons" when answering the other, very different question.
Overall, you seem to be attacking a straw man. You rail against the "moralist who can't see a difference between people who don't give to Oxfam and those who would let a child drown." But I'm not convinced that any such person actually exists.
Posted by: Richard | April 20, 2009 at 06:48 PM
First off: great article. Although I would say that since I mostly agree with you!
I think the key point where things go wrong is where you are discussing the maligned "sonofabitch". Now, you say that he is not a sonofabitch because he [i]does[/i] a bad thing. This I would agree with (I think moral luck considerations clearly rule that sort of evaluation out). However, this doesn't mean that the evaluation of his character must rest upon some non-moral ground. Even had he stayed at home, he still [i]would[/i] have let the child drown, had he gone out. That is, his character is bad precisely [i]because[/i] of his tendency to do Bad Things. Dostoyevsky's version might well have had [i]good[/i] character in that respect, even if he was so paralysed by something that he would in that instance have let the child drown.
Singer's argument then is just that not giving to charity is as much of a Bad Thing as is letting a child drown. The logic seems inescapable. You proceed from being directly present while the child drowns, to being nearby but [i]knowing[/i] that the child is drowning, to not being nearby but being able to phone someone to save the child, to being able to pay someone to save the child... and then you're there. The main difference I can see is that in the charitable case you are not saving a specific child. If there was a man with a gun in Africa with a website declaring that every hour he would shoot a child (videoed, of course) unless he was sent some money, I suspect people's sense of how immoral it would be not to pay would increase.
There is also the consideration that with charitable giving, other people may stick up the cost. If our favourite sonofabitch was on his way to an important meeting and there were several other people in the vicinity of the child, including a trained lifeguard (read: billionaire), it no longer seems so immoral to pass on by. However, in the case of charity, any given child might well be saved by someone else, even though in the aggregate, your contribution may lead to more children being saved.
What conclusion can we draw from this? Myself, I think that this is a case where philosophical ethics is genuinely prescriptive. I think this reasoning reveals (as Singer would have it) that we are indeed all people of fairly bad character. We [i]should[/i] be giving far more of our money to charity. However, I think the lack of specific engagement in the charitable case tends to confuse our intuitions. Also this idea is at odds with the psychological base of morality, which is more about protecting one's own community, and so our intuition tells us that people far away are less important.
Posted by: Michael Peyton Jones | September 08, 2009 at 03:01 PM
Great, I have to follow your blog, Thank you so much for post.
Posted by: ed hardy | November 23, 2009 at 02:30 AM
I read this article, This post was so great. Thanks for sharing.
Posted by: ed hardy | November 26, 2009 at 12:54 AM
I would say a couple things: I can see where sonofabithcness is much stronger in closer proximity. It is easier for us to not respond to people far away because it is harder for us emotionally to grasp the gravity of the suffering. The person close to the child would not have this harder obstacle to motivation to help and so if even with the situation pressed right up against his face he still didn't help, it would be more than just the mind's natural ability to underestimate the importance of situations far away, it would be a more generally callous or malicious disposition. And such a disposition makes him a sonofabitch and us more passive victims of a mind that can't be brought to care or act adequately in ways that we have not been conditioned evolutionarily to care or act (our brains are wired to help those near, not those who are effectively concepts to us).
But, nonetheless, if we can bring the realization of the real suffering far away to our minds more and more closely and yet still not act, we become more and more a sonofabitch ourselves, the more we steal ourselves against making an important sacrifice. And if we avoid really knowing about the suffering far away, either on purpose or implicitly, this bespeaks some degree of callousness and even active desire to remain callous. We deliberately allow ourselves to become more sonofabitch than we had to be.
So, while I think you do a nice job of helping elucidate one part of why we don't feel as bad about the non-donator as we do about the non-rescuer, I think there is still what you call an ethical critique of ignoring suffering far away regardless.
And I am really really unconvinced that we have no obligations without contracts. I find that a bewildering source of rationalizations that I can barely understand how anyone believes. I can understand if you are a radical subjectivist of some sort about morality. Maybe like Ayer in your example. But I don't get it otherwise and always thought that Thomson's article on abortion is an amazing feat of contortionism to justify abortion. She is willing to say there are no moral obligations even to cross a room and put your hand on their forehead when it could heal them. ALL to say under no conceivable circumstances could an abortion ever be morally criticized. It's warping all of morality out of fear that anyone would ever argue a woman had an obligation to carry to term. It's completely counter-intuitive to me. So, you have to make a case to me how we do not have moral obligations we did not actively sign up for first before I accept that. I mean, what is more basic to morality and obligations than that they involve things we have to do even against our strongest preferences sometimes?
Finally, on Nietzsche, I don't see him as having contempt for the heroically charitable. There is a lot of praise for those who deliberately go under to create something great in the future. There is a "will to power altruism" that I intend to write about. What Nietzsche is attacking is pity, the demoralization of the object of help, the attempt to gain power over someone with the disingenuous claim that you are only being selfless. That's what's so repulsive. And where does he explicitly talk about his superior humans being free to murder? What his goal is is that values and valuable things advance, even if in some means to this will be things that are hard to swallow. But that's not an anything goes policy for higher humans by any means.
So, those are my rough impressions for what they are worth.
Posted by: A Facebook User | September 04, 2011 at 03:24 PM
"I offer our good opinion of Singer and Singer's good opinion of himself (look at that picture), despite his drinks and shows and vacations, as evidence for my view."
Is this "evidence"? You seem to be saying that hypocrisy or atleast an at-ease hypocrisy (the profession of standards contrary to one's real character or actual behaviour) is the one flaw that mustn't be tolerated. It's a logical flaw perhaps but that wouldn't make it a higher order flaw in the opinion of a drowning child surely.
In fact why can't a lack of hypocrisy be a flaw - a lack of moral imagination - rather than a virtue?
Self-mortification over our hypocrisy is not necessarily productive in increasing our moral behaviour. Neither is lowering moral standards so that the hypocrisy disappears however. If our goal is to give more to charity than we currently do then perhaps a willingness to include hypocrisy as crucial to our moral development is the way to go.
Posted by: Humblewonderful.blogspot.com | October 22, 2011 at 06:48 PM
This could be off-topic, but if you're anywhere in or near LA, there are a lot of fundraising events for the benefit of the less fortunate where you can participate in. Donate your clothes and shoes like what Greenopolis.com did and be rewarded for your actions. http://youtu.be/jk1mH9JvRr0
Posted by: Account Deleted | December 31, 2011 at 07:01 AM